Those who favor limited government shouldn’t ignore the virtue factor.

Gage Skidmore / Wikimedia Commons (CC BY-SA 2.0)
American
politics is awhirl. Donald Trump’s transformation of the right is the
clearest sign of it. But the left is reborn, too—in outraged opposition
to the new president and with the example of Bernie Sanders pointing his
young admirers toward democratic socialism. Any ideology that fails to
adapt to this radically altered environment will die. Can
libertarianism, a philosophy at odds with Sanders’s democratic socialism
as well as Trump’s populist nationalism, survive?
Its formulas are well known: gun rights
and gay rights; lower taxes and less military spending; civil liberties
and maximum market freedom; open immigration and free trade. To critics,
all this adds up to an amoral, if not immoral, philosophy. But in the
pages of Reason last summer, two of libertarianism’s leading
minds set out to refute that impression and change the way the heirs to
classical liberalism think about themselves. William Ruger, the Charles
Koch Institute’s vice president of research and policy, and Jason
Sorens, founder of the Free State Project, introduced the concept of
“virtue libertarianism.”
The most dogged defenders of the right
to do as one pleases—to buy and sell freely, even drugs and sex—must
still draw and act upon moral distinctions, they argued. Not everything
that is uncoerced is good. Virtue is not only right in itself but is an
indispensable support to a free society. Vice, by contrast, breeds
dependence and servility: “we have set up for failure those who, for
whatever reason, suffer from greater impulsiveness, hedonism, laziness,
hopelessness, or greed,” Ruger and Sorens warned. Moral
interventions—not government interventions, but judicious praise and
blame—are essential to the health of society.
“To respect others, we must act
beneficently and generously toward them, not just refrain from taking
their freedom,” Sorens and Ruger contend:
In some cases, this means providing approbation and disapproval of certain choices to foster a culture consistent with human flourishing and a free society. For example, we should applaud those who pursue excellence in education, the arts, and sport as well as those who give their time and money to help their local communities. We should also not be afraid to hold up life-long committed marriage as an ideal for those with children. Harder in our current age, but equally important for a good society, we should not shy away from expressing disapproval of rent-seekers (those who demand special government privileges), those who harm themselves and their families through habitual intoxication or gambling, and those who idle away their time and talents in frivolous pursuits. … if someone wants to drink his life away, that should be legal but strongly disapproved or even shunned.
This is a libertarian alternative to tackling moral and
social problems through government. “Prohibitions, SWAT raids, and
prison terms for non-violent criminals are all poor ways to grow a
healthy moral ecology. Society has better, more-just alternatives.” The
same strictures all libertarians apply to the use of formal power are
upheld by virtue libertarians—but the moral pressure that others eschew,
they employ. The goal of virtue libertarianism is to regulate society
by manners and morals, as far as possible, rather than the blunt
instrument of law.
It’s an idea that would have been
familiar in an older America, and though its proponents don’t want to
turn back the clock—they recognize how much moral progress has been made
with respect to minority rights, for example—their vision is distinctly
traditional, rooted in an understanding of virtue that extends from
Aristotle to the American Founders. If Trump aims to make America great
again, Ruger and Sorens would make morality bourgeois again. But is that
enough to make libertarianism matter to the 21st century?
Just three years ago, libertarianism laid plausible claim to being the future of American politics. The New York Times magazine ran a cover story on what it called the “libertarian moment”; two months later, the cover of Time
proclaimed Sen. Rand Paul of Kentucky to be “the most interesting man
in politics.” The senator’s father, former Texas congressman Ron Paul,
had made libertarianism a powerful force in the Republican Party with
his presidential campaigns of 2008 and 2012, which won no primaries but
set records for small-donor fundraising and forged new cadres of
grassroots activists. If Ron Paul had achieved so much with a radical
libertarian message that often shocked GOP sensibilities, then surely
his more mainstream son would do even better.
Instead the younger Paul’s presidential
bid fizzled last year: he won fewer votes in Iowa than his father had
received four years earlier, and the senator ended his campaign before
New Hampshire. The 2016 Republican contest evolved into a struggle
between, on the one hand, two factions that had dominated the party
since the Reagan era—orthodox conservatives and establishment
moderates—and, on the other, the insurgent nationalism of Trump.
Libertarianism was left out.
That presented an opportunity for the
Libertarian Party. Since 2008, it had tried to capitalize on Ron Paul’s
success with Republican voters by nominating former GOP officeholders as
its presidential candidates: first former congressman Bob Barr; then
former New Mexico governor Gary Johnson in 2012. Last year the LP
nominated Johnson a second time, with another ex-GOP governor, William
Weld of Massachusetts, as his running mate. They had hopes, stoked by
polls throughout the summer, of winning 10 percent or more of the
popular vote. Even 5 percent would qualify the party for federal
matching funds.
The major-party nominees were the most
unpopular in history, and Republicans, it was thought, were especially
reluctant to support their man. How could a third-party ticket of two
Republican governors go wrong? Yet in the end Johnson and Weld received
only 3.3 percent of the popular vote. This was not entirely their fault:
however unpopular Trump and Clinton may have been, the Republican and
Democratic candidates represented such starkly contrasting policies and
values that even voters who considered the election a choice among evils
were apt to have a preference. The only way to stop the candidate they
feared more—whether that was Clinton or Trump—was to vote, reluctantly
or not, for the other major-party contender.
Still, the result was disappointing: was
this all that libertarians could hope for in the very best-case
scenario? Critics ascribed Johnson and Weld’s failure to their
campaign’s ideological tilt. Despite being ex-Republicans—though Weld,
to be sure, was a notably liberal GOP governor—the Libertarian
candidates made a “play entirely to the left,” as Austin Petersen, one
of Johnson’s former rivals for the LP nomination, told Reason.
The Johnson-Weld ticket was far from advancing anything like virtue
libertarianism or addressing conservatives’ fears that, as Ruger and
Sorens put it, “the movement will precipitate the unmooring of society
from its moral anchors.”
Presidential politics does not tell the
whole story of libertarianism’s fortunes, however. Since 2008, a small
but staunch bloc of libertarian-leaning Republicans has emerged in
Congress, including Reps. Justin Amash of Michigan and Thomas Massie of
Kentucky, as well as Senator Paul. Their allies include Reps. Dave Brat
of Virginia and Mark Sanford of South Carolina, and also the congressman
Trump picked to lead the White House Office of Management and Budget,
South Carolina’s Mick Mulvaney.
In the policy realm, libertarianism is
well-served by think tanks such as the Cato Institute, and the movement
has a presence on campuses in the form of Americans for Liberty and
Students for Liberty, two organizations launched in 2008. (Ron Paul’s
influence is obvious here, too.) The Koch brothers and their funding
network support libertarian causes, and key libertarian positions, such
as marijuana decriminalization and a more restrained foreign policy,
enjoy widening popular support.
Libertarianism has a toehold in American
public life. But can it ever have more than a toehold? Why, when it has
such impressive resources—billionaire financial backing, cadres of
intellectuals and activists—isn’t it more successful in politics or,
more importantly, in policy? How can libertarianism grow?
The question might seem irrelevant to
conservatives and progressives, the dominant ideological forces within
the major parties and—at least until Trump’s nationalism takes
institutional root—in the country as a whole. But there are reasons why
libertarianism should matter even to non-libertarians. The ideology’s
adherents help to keep both conservatives and progressives honest—and
from becoming intellectually complacent. They are exquisitely sensitive
to government abuses: libertarians are an early-warning system for
tyranny. They serve as a kind of conscience, too, in reminding the left
and the right, as they embark on value-laden programs of
government-directed social change, that there are costs even to pursuing
well-meaning policies, and that some powers are too great to be
entrusted even to good men in the name of a noble cause. Government can
be an instrument of self-righteous arrogance; libertarians of all kinds,
by the nature of their ideology, supply a balancing virtue of humility.
Conservatives, especially those of the
older sort, have a particular interest in the well-being of
libertarianism: libertarianism in some form is a vital component of
“fusionism”—the philosophy, promoted by National Review senior
editor Frank Meyer, that fuses elements of both libertarianism and
traditionalism. Indeed, the conservative movement that developed in the
early years of the Cold War saw itself as a return to classical
liberalism: Ronald Reagan told Reason in a 1975 interview, “If you analyze it I believe the very heart and soul of conservatism is libertarianism.”
What led to the emergence of a
libertarian movement separate from conservatism was a split over the
Cold War—libertarians were doves, orthodox conservatives tended to be
hawks—and the counterculture of the 1960s. The virtue libertarianism
that Ruger and Sorens promote is not marketed only to the right, but it
holds promise for repairing the breach that occurred with conservatives
over the hedonism of the ’60s. Conservative and libertarian realists
have already been close allies since the first Gulf War, jointly
opposing neoconservative wars and humanitarian interventionism.
But the greatest promise virtue
libertarianism holds is in returning the philosophy to its roots in the
classical liberalism of the 18th and 19th centuries, when liberalism
became one of the dominant political forces in the English-speaking
world (and to a lesser extent in France and elsewhere on the European
continent). What led to the rise of classical liberalism is worth
recounting. It began with religious liberty. Dissenting Protestants
demanded the freedom to worship according to their consciences and to
participate in civil affairs, though they often refused to extend such
tolerance to Catholics. Political liberals were inconsistent too, but as
a philosophy liberalism came to enshrine the principle of tolerance and
civil liberty for all believers—and, by extension, nonbelievers as
well. Far from being hostile to religion, classical liberalism was
fathered by faith and cherished its virtues.
In large part, that was true also of
classical liberalism’s economic program, as rising Protestant minorities
who excelled in commerce and industry sought to reform the
quasi-agrarian policies of the old order. Thrift and industriousness
were the virtues that underwrote the rise of capitalism, and as a
political and philosophical adjunct to the economic system, liberalism
provided a means to understand and defend the new commercial society.
A third critical component of classical
liberalism was its commitment to constitutional order—to expanding the
franchise and other political reforms but only so long as property and
other rights were secure. In this, liberalism was a reforming corrective
to the forces that opposed any widening of the electorate and at the
same time a check upon tendencies toward direct democracy and mob rule.
Political prudence was a cardinal virtue of liberalism at its best.
In all this, liberalism enjoyed the
support of the middle class—it was veritably the political expression of
the bourgeoisie. Yet it could command surprising support even among
working men, though it was not much loved by the farmer or clergy of the
established religion (which is why the Church of England was “the
Conservative Party at prayer”). In America, where Protestantism and
commerce held greater sway than in Britain, liberalism seemed almost to
be the heart of the country’s political tradition, to the point that
Americans who began to think of themselves as “conservatives” during the
Cold War nonetheless insisted that American conservatism was true
liberalism—and New Dealers had no right to the name. The word
“libertarian” was a conscious attempt to reclaim liberalism’s heritage.
The conditions that gave rise to
liberalism in the first place bear comparison to the politics of today.
The culture war between the religious right and the secular left is more
than a little reminiscent of the battles between Dissenters and
Establishment, and between Protestants and Catholics, in the European
politics of the past. The principles of commercial society stand again
in need of clarification and defense, not against feudalism,
mercantilism, or 19th-century socialism, but against crony capitalism,
administrative statism, and the mixed economies of the Keynesian left
and economically nationalist right. The old class basis of liberalism,
however, is imperiled: the truly bourgeois businessman and shopkeeper
has been replaced by the salaryman and bureaucrat. There are still
honest entrepreneurial capitalists, small and large, but they are
politically disorganized and outflanked. Finally, instead of a fight for
formal democratic representation, as in the 19th century, we now have a
situation in which a universally enfranchised adult electorate
nevertheless experiences frustration at a dwindling sense of control
over government.
The old liberalism was not an ideology
for scholastics and oddballs; it was bourgeois and mainstream.
Libertarianism today, on the other hand, is often a ménage of three
rather strange bedfellows. First is an unshakable but dispassionate
attachment to markets—an attitude of free-market technocracy more
enamored of formulas for liberty than with liberty itself (to say
nothing of virtue). Second, a pop-minded contrarianism that mocks the
pieties of traditionalism and political correctness alike. And finally,
on the Ron Paul side, there is an anti-elitist as well as
anti-government populism. These strains in themselves all have merits.
But they don’t add up to much political strength: the anti-government
populists have numbers but are also more right-leaning—and specifically
Trump-leaning—than the free-market technocrats and pop-culture
contrarians, who lean to the center or left. The technocrats have
academic respectability but little popular following, while the pop
libertarians include some moderately well-known celebrities—magician
Penn Jillette, for example, and Lisa Kennedy, a former MTV veejay now
seen on Fox Business Channel—but no one of the media stature of, say,
the former longtime host of The Apprentice.
There is today nothing quite like the old
bourgeois Protestant base to which the original liberalism appealed.
But there are at least four politically significant groups that seem
ripe for the virtue-libertarian message.
The first are center-right Republicans:
those disillusioned by neocon foreign policy; religious, or at least
respectful of religion, but not hard-line culture warriors; and
committed to the old Cold War conservative economic agenda of free
markets rather than economic nationalism. Fusionism was once the leading
philosophy among American conservatives—at least according to surveys
taken by Young Americans for Freedom in the 1960s—but today it’s without
an institutional home or voice, as movement conservatism has come to be
dominated by a new mix of right-wing tendencies that now includes
neoconservatism, Christian conservatism, and Trumpian nationalism.
The second group pulls together truly
“liberal” Democrats who are horrified by the excesses of identity
politics and by the prospect of the Democratic Party taking a hard-left
turn in reaction to Trump. These Democrats would have been primed for
the transition to neoconservatism once upon a time—and they may yet
become an element of a neocon revival if libertarians don’t get to them
first. These liberal Democrats are few in number but occupy some
important places in academia. They are staunchly committed to free
speech and the legacy of the Enlightenment. But they aren’t primarily
motivated by free-market economics. Virtue, however, is a language that
may appeal to them.
Third is a group that might be called the
religious center-right, which seeks a non-nationalistic political
ideology—one grounded in values rather than identity—and a resolution to
the culture war that affirms respect, tolerance, and some clearly drawn
lines for conscience in the public sphere.
Fourth, there are the “pragmatic
populists,” eager to pare back the power of Washington and the role of
credentialed elites in running red-state Americans’ lives, but who
nonetheless have the patience to pursue reformist policies. Theirs is a
slow-and-steady rather than impulsive populism, and the farsighted
prudence of virtue libertarianism may be a good fit for their
temperament.
The common ground of all these groups is
that they want a sober, serious, but not half-hearted or technocratic
political philosophy, one with enough strength to resist the excesses of
the left and right alike. Even if these elements can be brought
together by virtue libertarianism, they probably do not amount to a
majoritarian force. But a movement need not command a majority to shape
the way politics operates. The idea is to occupy the strategic center,
not with a narrow elite but with a wide segment of normal
Americans—above average in income and education, perhaps, but not
culturally rarefied in the way that celebrities, think-tank wonks, and
academics are. The ideology for this coalition is one that can appeal to
what once would have been called the newspaper-reading bourgeois
middle.
But isn’t this style of politics what Rand Paul attempted? And doesn’t his weak performance in 2016 suggest that it has no hope?
The opposite is true: if virtue
libertarianism had been widely known before Paul launched his candidacy,
he might have drawn considerable strength from it. Paul’s campaign was
hobbled from the start by the misidentification of the Kentucky
senator’s philosophy with the other “brands” known as libertarianism. To
conservative talk-radio hosts and even veteran Goldwater Republicans—as
I can attest from personal conversations—Rand Paul’s libertarianism
meant either his father’s no-compromise approach or Reason’s
countercultural proclivities. The idea that libertarianism could mean
something different—something mainstream, practical, and conservatively
virtuous—seemed hard for them to believe.
Republicans who reflexively dismissed
Paul and turned instead to more easily understood orthodox conservatives
like Ted Cruz would have had an easier time supporting someone like the
Kentucky senator if they had been familiar with virtue libertarianism.
But
virtue libertarianism can serve an even more important role in
politics. Clear ideas and publications or other institutions that
express such ideas are the launchpad of insurgent candidacies. Rand Paul
had the disadvantage of not having a distinct base of ideas to draw
upon: he had movement conservatism, which was more aligned with more
orthodox candidates, and he had versions of libertarianism that were
unrepresentative of his views and temperament.
The role of ideological institutions in laying the intellectual groundwork for political change cannot be exaggerated. Breitbart
was critical to the Trump phenomenon—just as its former editor, Steve
Bannon, is a key player in the new administration. Ron Paul’s rise as
Republican insurgent was foreshadowed by the online popularity of
“paleo-libertarian” institutions such as the Ludwig von Mises Institute
and LewRockwell.com, the latter published by one of Ron Paul’s former
chiefs of staff. National Review, of course, and its brand of
conservatism were instrumental in transforming the Republican Party of
the 1950s into the party of the Reagan era. The New Republic had been similarly important to progressives a century ago.
Classical liberalism was the hallmark
philosophy for a full century. Virtue libertarianism may not be able to
match that influence, barring the unlikely revival of the old
bourgeoisie. But it has the potential to revive commitments to liberty
and virtue alike in American politics. For that alone it deserves
attention and applause.
No comments:
Post a Comment